Skip to content

Book Review: Ethics Without Morals

by Bill Meacham on August 27th, 2014

I’ve been published again; this it is time a book review in Philosophy Now magazine.  Here is the link:  http://philosophynow.org/issues/103/Ethics_Without_Morals_by_Joel_Marks. For your convenience, I reproduce the whole thing below.

 

Regular readers of this publication will know that ex-columnist Joel Marks underwent quite a profound change of outlook with respect to the study of ethics and morality. Formerly a Kantian who worked out in some detail how the moral dictates of pure reason apply to particular circumstances, he is now a moral anti-realist, asserting that there are actually no moral dictates at all! Marks’ book, Ethics without Morals, is a readable exposition of his new position, which he calls ‘amorality’, after ‘atheism’. Just as atheism denies the objective existence of God, amorality denies the objective existence of morality.

As philosophers, we need to get clear on our concepts. What is morality? Marks’ answer: morality is a set of absolute and universal imperatives and prohibitions – a set of rules which everyone is obliged to obey. This set of imperatives is supposed to apply to all human beings at all times and places. The moral rules trump all other rules, and manifest in our feelings as spontaneous intuitions or impulses to obey or enforce them. The essence of morality is its universal, unchanging, and absolute authority in matters of human behavior. Following Kant, Marks calls moral imperatives ‘categorical’, meaning that they apply unconditionally, and independently of how we feel about them. In brief, morality is a set of obligations that we are all supposed to obey. This is what we mean by the term ‘morality’, by and large, in common language. And morality in this sense does not actually exist, says Marks.

The Genesis of Morality

Marks argues that there are several possible explanations for our belief in morality, and that the one that does not assume that morality exists makes a lot more sense than the others.

The first possible explanation for belief in morality is that God legislates it and gave us a conscience so we would know right from wrong. The second is that morality is a built-in feature of the universe, much like gravity, and we have developed an intuition to perceive it. The third is that the belief in morality was a useful evolutionary adaptation that lingers on even though it is no longer helpful.

The evolutionary explanation makes the best sense, according to Marks. Development of a sense of morals was evolutionarily adaptive for early humans because it enabled them to live cooperatively in groups. We evolved to believe in morality because we have to live with others in order to survive, and moral rules regulate how we get along together. A shared sense of morals makes for group cohesion, and those who live in cohesive groups survive and reproduce better than those who don’t. As primatologist Frans de Waal has noted, human societies are support systems within which temporary weakness does not automatically spell death (Our Inner Ape, 2005, p.187).

Crucially, this explanation does not require that morality actually exist in an objective sense; all it requires is that people believe it does. There is an obvious objection here, and to his credit Marks considers it: this explanation does not require that morality does not exist, either. The evolutionary argument is quite compatible with either of the other explanations. Against this possibility, Marks argues a form of Occam’s Razor: the evolutionary explanation alone is simpler and conceptually more economical than it would be in conjunction with either of the others. But Occam’s Razor alone is not enough to discredit them, so Marks must consider each independently.

Against the God explanation he cites Plato’s Euthyphro, in which Socrates argues that it makes more sense to say that the gods love what is right rather than that the right is whatever the gods love. Hence, morality (ie right and wrong), if it exists at all, exists independently of the gods (or of God). This leaves the second idea – that morality is a natural feature of the universe. Against this, Marks argues a number of things: that morality in this sense would be a set of commands without a commander, a nonsensical notion; that the only way of perceiving moral commands is through intuition, but different people have different intuitions, and there is no way to adjudicate between them; and, that there exists no plausible account of how an objective morality has any connection to the rest of the universe we know about – the idea is metaphysically incoherent. Of the three explanations, the only one left standing is the evolutionary one.

With so much at stake, one would expect an extensive discussion of just how our sense of morality may have evolved, the various ways it manifests in our lives and societies, the different flavors it takes, and so forth, along the lines of Jonathan Haidt, Stephen Pinker, Richard Joyce and others. In fact Marks spends remarkably little time defending the evolutionary view. That’s because he takes it to be well established already, and because he has his sights set on something more: why it is advisable not even to pretend that morality exists: “A clear-eyed review of the relative effects of believing and disbelieving in morality would move us to prefer an amoral regime” he says (p.38).

Meta-Ethical Marks

Marks is so eager to divest himself of anything that sounds like morality that he says there’s nothing we should do (because there are no moral ‘shoulds’), only what we want to do – a view of human nature that he calls ‘desirism’. All we ever do is what we want to do, he says. So the goal of his work is to convince us to desire amoralism.

In this effort Marks succeeds brilliantly. His chapter entitled ‘Might Amorality Be Preferable?’ includes an excellent rant against the defects of our typical sense of morality: morality makes us angry; it promotes hypocrisy; it encourages arrogance; it’s arbitrary, because there is no final justification for saying anything is right or wrong; it is imprudent, leading us to do things that have obviously bad consequences; it makes us intransigent, fueling endless strife; it is useless as a guide to life; and it leads philosophers to waste time on silly puzzles. By contrast, amorality is free of guilt, tolerant, interesting, explanatory and compassionate (when the blinders of blame are removed, we are free to consider others with an open heart), not to mention true. The upshot is that amorality is far more preferable. If you read only this chapter, you will have gained a lot.

Marks is here making a meta-ethical claim – a claim about the status of ethics – which claim I like to explain in terms of the language used to express it. That is, throughout the history of philosophy there have been two competing domains of discourse regarding ethics and morals, the Right and the Good. The Right pertains to duty and obligation: it refers to an obligation to obey moral rules; laws that are taken to be applicable universally and independent of one’s own preferences. The Good pertains to benefits and harms: it refers to consequences of actions that may be good or bad for the agent or others. In these terms, Marks’ claim (which I find persuasive) is that Goodness trumps Rightness – that it makes more sense to speak of ethics (ie, ideas of the best way to live in society) in terms of benefits and harms than to speak in terms of duty and obligation. He does not quite spell it out that way, but his preference for ‘goodness’ or ‘benefit’ language is clear from passages such as these:

  • “Believing this particular truth, that morality does not exist, will make things go better.” (p.2)
  • “Morality… does not exist and… it would be good for us to believe that.” (p.3)
  • “Abandonment of moral thinking and speaking… would be more effective in achieving… [a] common goal of maximally satisfying our considered desires.” (p.63)
  • “Morality breeds escalation of conflict, which is often to no one’s net benefit.” (p.66)

But if morality does not exist and it would be beneficial for us to quit speaking in moral terms, what is the alternative? What is the best way to live our lives? Marks’ answer is to pursue only what you desire after due consideration:

“We now… have a replacement criterion to guide our actions in general, to wit: Figure out what you really want, that is, the hierarchy of your desires all things considered, and then figure out how to achieve or acquire it by means that are themselves consonant with that prioritized set of your considered desires.” (p.53)

We might call this Marks’ categorical imperative, except that he is quite clear that it is not a moral command but only advice. In contrast to morality, ethical commands, he says, are hypothetical, their application being contingent upon what is desired. By this he means that you can legitimately offer advice such as, “If you want to be trusted, then you ought to be honest” (ethics), but you can’t legitimately tell someone that they must absolutely be honest, without context and without reference to what they want (morality). Amoralist ethics is therefore quite practical, in that it lends itself to evidence-based assessments of how best to proceed; and it is intrinsically motivating, because its advice is based on what you actually want, not on what someone else tells you to do.

Amoral Advice

There’s a lot to like here. There are a few rough spots, to be sure. There’s an egregious bit of sophistry on p.24, in which Marks assumes what he says needs proving. The discussion of evolution deserves a lengthier treatment. (Hmm, ‘deserves’. Am I making a moral judgment?) And I suspect that it would not be so easy to abandon our sense of morality, since it is built in by several hundreds of thousands of years of evolution. But these minor blemishes are far outweighed by the great service Marks has done in pointing out that the moral emperor has no clothes. The practicality of amoralism, in contrast to the intransigence of moralism, is quite appealing.

But I feel impelled to articulate one criticism: that Marks does not go far enough. He tells us to consider what we really want and then to act on our desires; but he gives no guidance about what to really want – by which I mean, no guidance about what it is important or advisable to want. What is important enough to care about? He asks us to pay attention to “our considered desires,” but on what basis shall we consider them? Certainly we all have competing desires. How then shall we evaluate them? How shall we decide which of the contestants to favor? What is the best thing (or even a pretty good thing) to desire with sufficient intensity that we are moved to actually strive to achieve it?

‘What’s the best thing to desire?’ is not a trivial question. Rather, it is one of the fundamental questions that philosophers have considered, since Socrates or earlier. Marks should at least offer some advice, then. That’s what philosophy, the pursuit of wisdom, is all about. (That’s a non-moral use of the word ‘should’, by the way: it means what is socially expected, not what is morally commanded.)

What would the advice be? My own view is that it would have to do with what leads us to a fulfilling and flourishing life. Thinkers as diverse as Kant and Socrates agree that the desire to survive, thrive and feel happy and fulfilled is fundamental and essential to all humans. If you disagree and think something else is more to be desired, then consider that in order to fulfill that alternative desire, you would have to survive and thrive at least enough to be able to attain it, and once you attained it, you would, I presume, feel happy and fulfilled. So functioning well enough to survive and thrive is the fundamental aim of all of us.

Given that premise, the philosophical question becomes an empirical one: what enables us to function well? How are we constituted, what is good for us, and what are we good for and good at? In short: What is human nature?

I won’t attempt to answer these questions here, but this shows there’s more to the story of ethics than just to do what you want after due consideration. We can for instance make generalizations about what makes most people happy or what promotes the welfare of most people, and we can generate advice based on those generalizations. Such advice, being empirically based, would have a great deal of force. I think Marks would agree that it would have much more force than moralistic judgments based on false metaphysical presuppositions.

In sum, Marks has produced a thought-provoking work. I have not described all of it. There is a chapter on how an amoralist would address the contentious issue of animal welfare, for instance. There is another chapter on various alternative ways to conceive of morality. Scattered throughout are hints that Marks doubts many of the usual conceptions of free will. Perhaps he will write about that topic in the future. If so, I expect to read it with as much pleasure as I had reading Ethics without Morals.

© Bill Meacham, 2014

Bill Meacham received his Ph.D. from the University of Texas at Austin, made his living as a computer programmer, systems analyst and project manager, and is now an independent scholar in philosophy. He is the author of How To Be An Excellent Human, and his writing can be found at bmeacham.com.

Ethics without Morals: In Defense of Amorality, by Joel Marks, New York and London: Routledge, 2013, 133 pages, ISBN: 978-0-415-63556-1

From → Philosophy

2 Comments
  1. Gene permalink

    It’s a well-written article, Bill, and on a very important subject, of course. These sorts of meta-ethical questions were occupying my mind on and off for some years. I agree with you on the minimal “survive and thrive” as a foundation for any other set of values. And I believe that any ethical imperative, that is workable and not self-delusional is a hypothetical one: “If you want X do Y”. But… there always be a dark-minded bunch that values death over life and non-being over being. Can we dismiss them simply because theirs is a minority view? Not really, because nearly any dominant view today was a minority view at some point in the past. So what can we, (the survive and thrive faction) say to them? Not much, except to invite them into our values – “Hey, choose the fulfilling life, it’s so much better!” And if that does not work and they only want to quietly off themselves, well, that’s their problem. But when they want to take us out too, it becomes our problem. This is not just theoretical – the ISIS beheading experts are one example of the kind of folks I’m talking about.

    Personally, I’m in the Nietzschean camp regarding values:
    “Whatever has value in our world now does not have value in itself, according to its nature—nature is always value-less, but has been given value at some time, as a present—and it is we who gave and bestowed it. Only we have created the world that concerns human beings!” (GS 301)

    But “we” in Nietzsche’s quote is a rather assorted bunch and some of the values thus created can be in a sharp conflict with others. How to deal with such conflicts is another sizable issue.

  2. Jim Kutz permalink

    I happened upon your blog after reading your piece on elementary physics and quantum mechanics. This led me to your review of Joel Marks’ book, Ethics without Morals. You raised in your review the question I raised as I read it. Exactly what is the basis upon which we build human morality? Though I haven’t read your book on ethics and a fulfilled human life, your assumptions about what constitutes a moral basis are revealed in your review of Marks: the evolutionary drive for cooperation and social stability to insure that our species thrives. If I am correct, then a fuller argumentation about this as a moral basis is needed to convince me. Maybe you do that in your book, but I want to present some issues I find with a naturalistic, humanistic view of morality.

    My reasons are associated with three large issues. The first is that evolution is not necessarily a shining example of a morality that is life-friendly. Like it or not, this evolutionary program has inherited the same critique that was once aimed at deity, i.e. theodicy. Only now instead of “If there is a good God, how can there be so much predation and pain in natural existence?”, it’s, “If there is a good evolution, how can there is so much predation and pain in natural existence?” Not to be pedantic, but emphatic, the predation and pain of nature started right from the beginning, long before humans appeared on the scene. And there are the usual evolutionary slogans that “only the adaptable survive” and “the survival of the fittest” which more than hint that evolution is not so good for a whole lot of life.

    In this line of thinking the appearance of humanity has not offered encouragement. That brings us to all the contemporary environmental issues as well as the tremendous evils that we experience every day in human relationships. Therefore, I would call into question your hugely positive embrace of evolution and all the good things it seems to offer without a deep address to the very negative things that have and continue to try to destroy life that are also built into evolution.

    My second reason relates to what seems on your part to be so optimistic about humanity and our capability to act morally. My assumption is that whatever is touched by humanity is touched by all aspects of humanity both its tremendous noble spirit and its disturbingly deprived evil. We are a living moral paradox, capable of the whole range of behaviors, and every generation and individual seems to have to learn how to deal with this reality. I am also not optimistic that things are getting better and better. Evolution does not have such a nuanced moral compass. It is so broad that it would have been satisfied if Hitler had won the war as long as the species survives. To my knowledge there is no fine tuning of morality in nature unless you count human imagination as part of nature. If religion is the outworking of nature’s built-in will-to-life, it was a pretty good trick to keep us ticking. In fact my contention is that in the western world at least, we are holding to a morality that is based upon a memory of an ancient religion about a relational loving, creating God only without the loving, creating God. If one contends that religion is evolution’s way to get human thriving, a modern secular humanist will be in the same boat, only without relationality, transcendence and absolutes. I mean, how can one lovingly relate to a mindless, heartless process such as evolution, as powerful as it is?

    My third point should support what I’ve said in the first two. Here I offer a larger reason from those above that seldom, if ever, is dealt with by scientists or philosophers in regard to the human future. This results from the grasp we have of our place in the universe. The scientific consensus is something like this: The universe will continue to expand until dead where no biotic or whatever other life might be conceived can exist. It will be so attenuated, dark, and cold that one can say it ends at zero, nothingness. Before that, human life will be long gone with the expansion of the sun as it goes into its red giant phase. Many extinctions have occurred throughout geological history. Is that not a certain possibility for humans much sooner than the sun’s demise? So, the premise that evolution requires us to be moral and offers us human thriving as a reason, simply does not stand the test of this reality. Humanity will come to nothing the same as evolution and the universe. As far as I’m concerned whoever does not address this reality of the physical universe, has little to say about ultimate human values and meaning.

    Some people have discovered that they can chose against nature such as in suicide or human euthanasia, or in getting a vital organ transplant. Our dear friend Ray Kurzweil believes that we can get humans to live forever. For some there is good logic in ending all of this non-sense. Others want to extend or tinker with life and do nature one better. So, there is a rational dilemma (maybe even a moral one) for many humans. How tightly do we want to embrace the will-for-life built into nature. With all ending at zero anyway the choices are truly limited. One possibility might be to simply thrive a while the best we can, maybe share our thriving with others, do as nature dictates, and then die in old age or as accident or stupidity insert themselves. Evolution as basis for human morality does not answer the larger question of human meaning, nor morality, except in a very narrow scope. Besides, I think your scenario might assume that things are going well, that society is stable, and there is enough material wealth for all. The moment that stability is overturned, “all hell breaks loose!”, as the saying goes. This is building castles in the sky, just to get by, until we die.

    Another option is to accept that there is no meaning or anything large enough to address that meaninglessness and conclude that therefore there is no basis for morality. I still come back to the question of why be moral following someone’s tenuous assumptions and interpretation of morality, if we are dallying within an ultimately nihilistic reality, why? And, if a faith such as Christianity offers a good and true life in this world and a new life in the future, but it is only a ploy of evolution to help us thrive and multiply, why is there this force that is so intent on going against the grain? And why should we march to its music?

Leave a Reply

Note: XHTML is allowed. Your email address will never be published.

Subscribe to this comment feed via RSS